In progress (happy to share)
Paper on peer disagreement & the normativity of assertion (under review)
Suppose that it is reasonable for you to think that I am just as likely as you to know whether p is true. Suppose too that you have warrant to assert that p is false. Now, if you observe me assert p, do you have warrant to object by asserting not-p in response? Answering this question leads to a surprising conclusion: the epistemic norm of assertion is incompatible with Conciliationism about peer disagreement.
Paper on disagreement, testimony, and assertion (under review)
There are two questions at the core of the epistemology of disagreement. The first concerns whether learning of peer disagreement provides one with a higher-order defeater. The second concerns when it is reasonable to believe that someone is an epistemic peer. This paper focuses on the second question while assuming that Conciliationism — that is, an affirmative answer to the first question — is true. In doing so, I hope to produce a surprising result: if you are a Conciliationist, then you should be an Anti-Reductionist about testimony-based justification and a proponent of the thesis that assertion is governed by a robustly epistemic norm. In big picture terms, this paper hopes to show how various core issues in social epistemology, such as peer disagreement, testimony-based justification, and the norm of assertion, are more intimately connected than has previously been recognized.
Paper on the norm of assertion, functionalist norms, & practical stakes (under review)
Many epistemologists think that classical invariantism (CI) is the default view of the semantics of ‘know’, and many think that knowledge is the norm of assertion (KNA). The shiftiness dilemma challenges the claim that CI and KNA are compatible. What, then, is required to defeat the shiftiness dilemma? A recent proposal suggests that an appeal to a functionalist framework of normativity can vindicate CI/KNA compatibility. In this paper, I argue that this proposal suffers from a fatal defect. While a functionalist framework may account for epistemic normativity, it cannot be account for practical normativity. As a result, the functionalist framework cannot ground CI/KNA compatibility.
“No Doubt: Hinge Epistemology & Disagreement-Based Skepticism”
Conciliationism is the view which states that peer disagreement is epistemically significant: when I learn that an epistemic peer disagrees with me about some issue, this defeats the justificatory status of my prior belief. In this paper, I raise a problem for conciliationism, then offer a solution. The problem is that the view appears to lead to disagreement-based skepticism. The solution involves an appeal to hinge epistemology. In short, what I argue is that if one is a conciliationist, one should be a hinge epistemologist as well.
“Accepting Defeat”
There are two questions at the core of the epistemology of disagreement: Does evidence of peer disagreement defeat? When is it reasonable to believe that someone is an epistemic peer? If one responds to the first affirmatively, then one is a Conciliationist, but what sort of Conciliationist depends on how one responds to the second. In this paper, I argue for two claims: Conciliationism is in conflict with the claim that the norm of assertion is governed by a robustly epistemic norm (ENA), but the most plausible version of Conciliationism assumes that ENA is true. The result is a self-defeat problem that is conceptual in nature: it is not only novel to the peer disagreement literature, but it poses a stronger challenge to Conciliationism than the more familiar, epistemic self-defeat problem.
“Systematic Disagreement & the Norm of Assertion”
Sometimes, we disagree over things like how much we owe at the end of a meal. Sometimes, we disagree over things like philosophy, politics, or religion. The first is a mundane disagreement. The second are systematic. Some think that the nature of systematic disagreement requires us to revise our conception of the normativity of assertion. Call this disagreement-based revisionism. For example, Goldberg (2015) argues that systematic disagreement shows that the content of the norm of assertion is context-sensitive. Fleisher (2021), on the other hand, argues that it shows that there are different types of assertion associated with different types of norms. In this paper, I argue that disagreement-based revisionism is misguided and unmotivated. It is misguided because the traditional account does a better job explaining the evidence. It is unmotivated because the problem of systematic disagreement is more far reaching than previously realized.